Frank Stella's work has been
at the centre of discussions around painting for almost forty
years. In that time Stella's work has undergone a number of
transformations that have brought his practice into an arena
of construction that nevertheless is centred in pictorial practice.
The occasion of an exhibition of a single piece, Die Marquis
Von O, is also the opportunity to review Stella's practice in
the light of his past work having been such a crucial defining
aspect for contemporary painting. What seems to be at stake
in Stella's work, now and historically, is a testing of the
defining terms of what we understand to be 'painting'. However,
the term 'painting', especially as used in the critical writings
of Clement Greenberg and Michael Fried, offers both a perspective
and a problematic for discussion when addressing a work such
as Die Marquis Von O. For what is characteristic of Stella,
since the nineteen sixties, is a questioning of 'painting' within
the defining terms of a hostility to it and on the very borders
of what might constitute its specificity. The relationship between
Greenberg's and Fried's critical positions in the light of Stella's
work typifies this. That debate was a struggle to maintain painting
as a medium in the light of its dissolution in the face of the
criteria of Minimalism. Stella's 'painting' was central to that
discussion because of his employment of qualities and means
which sought to extend the terms of painting, without entering
into a speculation as to the end of painting. Fried's writings
in the sixties illustrate the problem well. Perhaps it was not
the practice of painting which was a risk in the light of Specific
Objects but the versatility that the term painting itself had
within a wider critical practice. With this in mind it is important
to review the criteria of that period to attempt to understand
how Stella was attempting to transform his practice as a 'painter'.
In Michael Fried's Shape as Form: Frank Stella's Irregular Polygons
(Art and Objecthood, University of Chicago, 1998). shape necessitated
Fried using a modified vocabulary to account for developments
in the paintings of Stella and Kenneth Noland. As Fried says:
The discovery shortly before 1960 of a new mode of pictorial
structure based on the shape, rather than the flatness, of the
support. With the dissolution or the neutralizing of the flatness
of the support by the new optical illusionism, the shape of
the support - including its proportions and its exact dimensions
- came to assume a more active, more explicit importance than
ever before (my italics).
Fried assigns the discoveries he attributes to shape to a 'new
mode of pictorial structure' and started his essay by saying
that shape itself could be considered as a medium. The breakdown
of the term painting, as set down by Greenberg, to accommodate
a perceptual oscillation between depicted and literal shape
does not just reflect how restrictive Greenberg's account of
painting was at that time. Greenberg's protection of optical
illusion as an event that takes place within the rectangular
limits of a painting now seem naive. But the complexity of Fried's
thinking, not only around shape but also in terms of an idea
of medium and the position of the 'beholder', begins to open
out into a discussion about the pictorial. It was evident that
the criteria of painting at that time could not hold the ground
upon which his discussion, and the practice of the artists he
was addressing was founded.
Depicted shape, in Fried's account, is left as a simple matter
of a struggle for the mind to acknowledge shape as an object,
in terms of the shaped canvas and its 'illusionist' properties
as a pictorial figure. 'Irregular polygons' as a term here is
crucial. A four sided figure that is not a rectangle will have
the potential to be seen 'illusionistically' as a figure in
a plane denoting an inclination away from the picture plane,
a phenomena which Fried acknowledges. However the illusion involved
here is not simply a matter of perspectival forces. A polygon
seen as a figure in an inclined plane can still maintain parallel
sides in the plane of recession, as opposed to the sides converging
upon a vanishing point. Illusion here is not a simple matter.
The qualities that are at work here can be assigned to projection
drawing systems such as axonometrics and obliques. Yve-Alain
Bois discusses such qualities in his essay .Lissitzky, Mondrian,
Strzeminski: Abstraction and Political Utopia in the Twenties.
In relation to axonometrics he says:
The use of axonometric projection in Lissitzsky's famous Proun
paintings was explicitly targeted against the illusionistic
device of one-point perspective..............Instead of an authoritarian
imaginary space, which hypnotized the spectator, Lissitzky proposed
an abstract space without a single point of view. The space
is still imaginary, to be sure (which is perhaps why Lissitzky
abandoned painting in the mid-twenties), but the spectator is
left free to reconstruct potential volumes out of the floating
vectors. The viewer receives no blueprint for reading, no fulcrum
for perception. Lissitzsky considered deliberate spatial ambiguity
to be the Aufhebung (sublation) of perspectival illusionism
- that is, in Hegelian terms, both its dialectal transformation
and its overcoming.
I am not suggesting here that Stella's use of shape constitutes
a utopian project with political ambitions on the scale of Lissitzy's.
I am suggesting though that Stella was perhaps addressing issues
which could challenge the authoritative status of Greenberg's
position to illusion in the nineteen sixties.
Projection drawing systems have a further relation to depiction.
Elsworth Kelly featured very little, if at all, in the high
modernist debate around painting so far referred to in this
essay. Kelly's use of shape in his work demonstrates an active
relationship to the determining properties of projection drawing
systems. His photographs of shadows are an important aspect
of his work and at times they generated a schema from which
he would often make paintings. Shadows are a literal demonstration
of projection, i.e. the falling of light upon a object creating
a shadow which is a two dimensional shape generated from a three
dimensional form. The shape generated reflects the properties
of the object of which it is an index and is not dependent upon
the position of the observer. This quality is furthered in axonometric
drawing where the depiction of a form can contain actual properties
of the object depicted, as opposed to how those properties appear
from a single point of view. This leads to a conclusion that
projection systems are object based in their workings as opposed
to the situation of a viewer based system like perspective.
Such an account of shape in terms of pictorial structure leads
to a further account of pictorial practice which increasingly
from the nineteen seventies is at the heart of Stella's work.
Collage and construction increasingly become the operational
criteria of his work. His working practice thus begins to suggest
a proximity to cubism as well as the European utopian movements.
With these historical examples, projection systems play a role
alongside a thinking of the material working of pictorial space
that extends from painting through collage to construction.
With Cubism this was perhaps just an implication. In Juan Gris'
paintings there is often the use of a convergence of oblique
projections which, while preserving the integrity of the picture
plane, place the spectator in number of implied positions. Collage
in cubism further extends the idea of space as a series of possibilities
of pictorial structure in terms of which the spectator must
negotiate a series of imaginary positions. Here the 'real' object
was appropriated into a schema where projections are operating
in terms of relationship to nominal objects, rather than within
a structure that is a direct address to the spectator's position.
It is with this mind that an understanding of Stella's present
work can be perhaps achieved. My implication here is that Stella's
practice is one of working within ideas of pictorial structure
rather than within the material limits of painting as defined
by high modernism. Leo Steinberg's essay the Flatbed Picture
Plane (in Other Criteria, London and New York 1972) attributed
the breakdown of Renaissance world space as a disruption of
the 'head to toe' picture space. His advancement of this disruption
as the flatbed picture plane, as the horizontal plane of operation
and information, was at the same time a critique of Greenberg's
picture plane and optical illusion which depended upon the verticality
of the spectator and the painting and thus agreed an 'implied
act of vision'. Even in 1972 Steinberg saw Stella's work as
distinct from Greenberg's criteria and also perhaps from Fried's.
As Steinberg says:
The flatbed picture plane lends itself to any content that does
not evoke a prior optical event. As a criterion of classification
it cuts across the terms 'abstract' and 'representational' ,
Pop and Modernist. Color field painters such as Noland, Frank
Stella and Elsworth Kelly, whenever their work suggests a reproducible
image, seems to work with the flatbed picture plane, i.e. one
which is man-made and stops short of the pigmented surface;
whereas Pollock's and Louis's pictures remain visionary, and
Frankenthaler's abstractions, for all their immediate modernism,
are - as Lawrence Alloway recently put it - 'a celebration of
human pleasure in what is not man-made.'
The use of the axis of nature/culture in Steinberg's criteria
brought with it a thinking through of the implications of technology
to pictorial structure. As Steinberg says:
The flatbed picture plane makes its symbolic allusion to hard
surfaces such as tabletops, studio floors, charts bulletin boards
- any receptor surface on which objects are scattered, on which
data is entered, on which information may be received, printed,
impressed - whether coherently or in confusion.
The logic of Steinberg's thinking, in hindsight, is uncanny.
The controlling interface of the computer is now universally
organised around the idea of the desktop - a surface where any
number of categories of information and objects can be brought
together and manipulated.
And so to Die Marquis Von O. It is one piece comprised of seven
canvases. Their sizes differ and are arranged around a symmetry
with the largest at the centre, flanked on each side by three
canvasses which diminish in dimension, the smallest being on
the extreme left and right of the work. The cacophony of elements
in the work are arranged in a faux collage of flat and distorted
grids - flat and spatial vectors. The overlaying of elements
seems not to be within a recessional, natural space, a depth,
but instead within a thickness of the support. The space of
the picture appears weightless; elements weave in and out of
each other and seem to have been cut and pasted into a logic
of endless addition and modification. Elements appear and reappear
in a ceaseless freefall. This is not a field of a finite compositional
telos but more a weightless domain of endless possible unfoldings
within a space of inspecific scale or relation.
At this point it is worth introducing an idea of the current
phase of capital and its spatial logos, particularly in reference
to Gilles Deleuze's text, Postscripts on the Societies of Control
(L’autre journal, May 1990). The crux of this essay is
Foucault’s identification of the disciplinary structures
of enclosure instituted by Napoleon which were rapidly outmoded
and modified after World War II. The new phase is dubbed a society
of control, in direct relation to that of the disciplinary model
but with systems and qualities altogether transformed. Societies
of control do not operate in terms of the disciplinary model
of time frames within a closed system, instead there is free
fall through a number of confinements, indexed and coded in
different ways. One such example is the corporate wage structure
which modulates each salary according to the challenges of a
bonus system replacing a former salary structure incremented
through service to the company. Thus confinement as characterized
by a spatial telos for a phase that we are now passing into
is inaccurate, and at its best, as an index, it is nostalgic.
Deleuze characterizes this change from one structure to another
thus:
“The old monetary mole is the animal of the spaces of
enclosure, but the serpent is that of the societies of control.
We have passed from one animal to the other..”
Something of the transformation that Deleuze describes can be
seen to be at work in Stella's recent painting. Perhaps it is
not by chance that Peter Halley refereed to Stella's earlier
'geometric' paintings as typifying a relationship to a disciplinary
model of space in terms of Foucault's ideas. A work like Die
Marquis Von O marks a dramatic move away from that telos of
confinement and reduction toward a logic of the 'painting' and
the picture being in excess of itself, perhaps more as a type
of hysteria than optimism. The relation that Die Marquis Von
O draws with the operational mode of the computer's visual space
is apparent. Collage, cloning and endless manipulation within
a structure of montage giving rise to a ceaseless continuum
are the working conditions of both the computer and a piece
like Die Marquis Von O.
We could conclude with a question. Is the issue at stake in
a work like Die Marquis Von O the position of the spectator;
active in terms of beholding the unfolding structure of the
work on the one hand, or passive in being rendered motionless
by the force of its effect, as spectacle, on the other?
|